L.2 - intro

LESSONS

L.2 - The subject fraudulent commission 

(I: Objective imputation)

 

L.2 video

L.2 -txt

STRUCTURE

I. Meaning of the so-called "objective imputation":
1.The judgement of human conduct as typical.
2.Types of mere activity and types of result.
Causality and "objective imputation".
II.The modern doctrine of "objective imputation". Criteria and rules of objective imputation of results.

What have you done (I)

A person lying helplessly on the ground, together with the perception of the bang and the fracture of the window, immediately raises another question:

What have you done? That is, if what has happened is not a mere process of nature, but an action, we ask ourselves what class behaviour has been performed. Almost without realising it, we come to evaluate the conduct in some way: loaded with meaning as a homicide.

The distinction between "explaining" and "understanding", corresponding to the so-called "empirical" and " evaluation" judgements, respectively, has been used for a long time. Any of us can look out of the window and say: "it is raining", "it is sunny", "it is snowing"...; but we can also say: "I don't like it raining", "it is a beautiful day". In the latter two, a value judgement is made, an understanding of the day as bad or good. In the first three, you simply explain what you see. In our initial case, I can say: "that person has a dagger stuck in his chest", "the gradual loss of 1,500 ml of blood has caused a cardiac-respiratory collapse", "a heavy body is attracted towards the centre of the Earth...". These are statements made by scientists (doctors, physicists, or simply the spectator), who describe or explain. But they do not understand.

When freedom enters the picture, then we understand reality. Then a factor comes into play, freedom, which escapes mere explanation. And only then, only if I understand, can I assess reality. Thus, I will say: "someone has killed him".

The assertions of law require empirical judgements: it is necessary to know whether someone has died, whether there were poisonous substances in the body, whether there was a cardiac-respiratory collapse... Such judgements explain that a person has died, but not that someone has killed him or her.

In order to say that someone has killed someone else, the conduct in question must be confronted with a criminal rule (the relevant article of the penal code). If we conclude in the affirmative, this conduct is objectively typical, to which we must also add whether the same conduct is also subjectively typical(L.3). It is a question, in final, of judging (assessing) whether or not the conduct in question belongs to the type of conduct that the legislator intended to prevent by means of this rule. It is the evaluative criteria that are suitable for answering the question of the meaning of the conduct.

However, for a certain period of time, criminal doctrine (naturalistic positivism) was dominated by the pretension of providing an explanation of human conduct based on mere empirical causality(C.25). This is an inadequate means for the intended purpose: to understand human conduct. Nowadays, thanks to the doctrine of "objective imputation", the idea has become widespread that it must be evaluative criteria that provide an answer to the question of the meaning of conduct. Despite this employment of evaluative criteria, it is still common to see resource to empirical causality as a prior step for the imputation of the conduct. This is acceptable if we understand that this requirement of causality cannot replace those criteria, which are the ideal means of understanding human conduct.

These evaluative criteria can be summarised in the following statement: a conduct is typical in the sense of goal when it displays a relevant risk within the meaning of the subject. In other words: that it deploys a sufficiently relevant risk from the point of view of the subject in question (mere activity and attempt types), and furthermore that this risk is realised on the result (in types of result). Let's look at it in C.21.

L.2-NB-AZUL

On the origin of the theory of objective imputation: this doctrine comes from Civil Law (Larenz, 1927), from where authors such as Honig (1930) apply it to Criminal Law. Years later it was reworked by other authors (Roxin, 1970). It is now a commonly accepted doctrine.

L.2 - Desplegable

C.24

"On 5.9.1998, at around 0.30 a.m., on the Vía Carpetana in Madrid, an argument took place between Imanol, with National Identity Card issue 000, who was 29 years old, born on 7.12.68 and Blanca. In the course of the argument, the former pushed the latter, causing her to fall to the ground. Claudio helped his girlfriend Blanca to get up, at which point Imanol hit Claudio against a parked car and, taking out a sharp object from his clothes, stabbed him with it with great energy from below and from left to right in the lower left dorsal region, at the level of dorsal 11. Imanol stabbed him in the back. Claudio suffered a penetrating wound to the thorax, breaking his 10th rib, which caused hypovolemic shock. He died at 8 p.m. the same day at the Gómez Ulla Hospital. The injuries caused by the stab wound were not fatal, but led to Claudio' s death, due to the time elapsed from the moment of the aggression until the thoracic CAT scan".

(STS 28 January 2005; pte. Martínez Arrieta; RJ 2005, 911).

AA.2

Criminal law distinguishes between status crimes (crimes of circumstances) and causation crimes (or crimes of result). Both must be defined in a statute, from agreement with the principle of legality.
Crimes of circumstances would be some crimes such as drug offences. This is the case of the offence of "narcotic addiction", where the mere fact of being a drug addict constitutes in itself an offence. These are controversial offences, particularly in relation to the 8th and 14th amendments of the US Constitution.
The offences of result usually require causation. Causation is relevant to the extent that the actus reus incorporates in its description a result as an effect of the prohibited action (death in the case of murder, for example). The first analysis to determine causation is carried out by means of the "but-for" criterion. That is to say, to determine whether or not the result (note its proximity to the formula of the condicio) would have been verified if the action had not taken place. However, in order to avoid unlimited causal chains, only the so-called "legal causes" are taken into account: the closest, the most direct or the most substantial cause. These are the criminally relevant causes. The causal link can be denied in two cases: when an agent's conduct has been replaced by intervening events, or when the circumstances have not followed a probable natural course, but have been deviated by factors beyond the control of the perpetrator (unforeseeability). The categories of objective imputation, which are so elaborate in continental law, can be found here partly in the discussion of causation.
On the principle of legality: US v. Hudson and Goodwin (SC US 11 US 7 Cranch 32) 1812; on status crimes: Powell v. Texas (392 U.S. 514, 88 S. CT. 2145, 20 L. Ed. 2d 1254) 1968; on causation crimes: Regina v. Martin Dyos (Central Criminal Court Crim. Law Rev. 660-662) 1972.

VOCABULARY

  • But for causation 
  • Causation crimes
  • Duties
  • Foreseeability
  • Legality
  • Intervening events
  • Status crimes

For starters: Roxin, Criminal Law. Parte general, I. Fundamentos. La estructura de la teoría del delito (trans. Luzón/Díaz/de Vicente), Madrid, 1997, § 11.

For further information: Puppe, La imputación objetiva ( trans. García Cavero), Granada, 2001. 

Monograph: Gimbernat Ordeig, Delitos cualificados por el result y relación de causalidad (1966), Madrid, 1990.

N.21 Meaning of the so-called "objective imputation".
N.22 The modern doctrine of "objective imputation".